Quantum redactiones paginae "Utilitarismus" differant

Content deleted Content added
mNo edit summary
No edit summary
Linea 3:
[[Fasciculus:Singer1.jpg|thumb|170px|[[Petrus Singer]], philosophus moralis [[Australia]]nus.]]
'''Utilitarismus'''<ref>Victor Cathrein (1915) ''Cursus philosophicus,'' §§ 26, 126, 134. Herder;
Christian Helfer (1991) ''Lexicon Auxiliare'', p. 602. Tertia editio valde emendata. Verlag der Societas Latina; ''Lexicon Recentis Latinitatis'', p. 390. Lampertz, 1998; Jose Juan de Col (2007) ''Diccionario auxiliar español-latino para el uso moderno del latín'', p. 1099. Instituto Superior “Juan XXIII”.</ref><ref>Apud scriptores Anglophonos interdum '''utilitarianismus''', sicut Ad. Tanquerey, ''Synopsis Theologiae Dogmaticae Fundamentalis: Ad mentem S. Thomae Aquinatis, Hodiernis moribus accommodata: de Vera Religione, de Ecclesia Christi, de Fontibus theologicis'' (Baltimorae, 1896), 35–36: "declarat utilitarianismum esse systema non solum immorale, sed etiam prorsus inefficax."</ref> est theoria [[ethica normativa|normativa]], quae optimam actionem [[moralitas|moralem]] docet in [[utilitas|utilitate]] quam maxima positam esse. Utilitas autem varie definiri potest, prout de unius hominis utilitate privata (id est: utilitarismus privatus) aut de hominum societatis utilitate agitur (id est: utilitarismus socialis). [[Ieremias Bentham]], auctor utilitarismi, deducta miseria omnium quaibet actione implicatorum, coacervatione [[voluptas|voluptatis]] utilitatem definivit. Quam notionem quantitativam utilitatis [[Ioannes Stuart Mill]] ita amplificavit, ut, omissis singulis actionibus, animum ad qualitatem attenderet: moralitas utilitaristica [[felicitas|felicitate]] aestimari oportere, felicitatem autem non solum in voluptate sed etiam in absentia miseriae consistere; infelicitatem contra ex miseria et absentia voluptatis constare.<ref>Mill 1861: 10.</ref> In utilitarismo Milliano actio moralis "felicitate" et "voluptate" aestimatur. Quae ratio ab adversariis reicitur, quod nimio opere [[hedonismus|hedonismum]] redoleat. Utilitarismus, item ac [[ethica]] in genere, ad hominem pertinet, quamquam sunt qui "felicitati" [[animal]]ium quoque cavere velint.<ref>Singer 2001.</ref>
Utilitarismus est forma [[consequentialismus|consequentialismi]], cuius adsectatores consecutionibus cuiuslibet actionis [[bonum (ethica)|bonum]] et [[malum (ethica)|malum]] metiuntur. Quae opinio comparari vel coniungi potest cum [[ethica virtutis]], in qua [[virtus]] bonum morale esse putatur. Nonnulli credunt consilia hominum etiam momentum ethicum habere. Utilitarismus ab aliis consequentialismi generibus, sicut [[egoismus ethicus|egoismo ethico]], distincte hoc differt, quod omnes rationes aequabiliter respicit. Suasores utilitarismi inter sese differunt, utrum actus singulares cum utilitate congruere oporteat (id est [[utilitarismus actionis]]), an actores regulas ethicas sequi debeant (id est [[utilitarismus regularum]]). Utilitaristae praeterea dissentiunt, in ratiocinatione utilitatis utrum de tota an de mediana felicitate agatur.
 
== Historia utilitarismi ==
Utilitarismus privatus et utilitarismus socialis eodem fere tempore instituti sunt, hic apud [[Sina|Sinenses]], ille apud [[Graeci antiqui|Graecos antiquos]]. [[Micius]] enim, philosophus Sinensis aequalis [[Socrates|Socrati]] per 2500 annos in oblivionem adductus,<ref>Mei 1934.</ref> opes et divitias hominumque auctum prosperitati prodesse docuit. Apud Graecos [[Aristippus]], philosophus [[Cyrenae]]us, qui anno fere 400 a.C.n. floruit, ac centum fere annis post [[Epicurus]], homo [[Athenae|Athenis]] in philosophia versatus, [[hedonismus|hedonismo]] faverunt voluptatemque summum finem hominis esse docuerunt.
Origo [[hedonismus|hedonismi]] ab [[Aristippus|Aristippo]] et [[Epicurus|Epicuro]] trahi solet, qui felicitatem solum bonum habebant.
 
Bentham autem libro ''An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation'' anno [[1789]] edito utilitarismum condidisse putatur. Post eum utilitaristae gravissimi sunt Ioannes Stuart Mill, [[Henricus Sidgwick]], [[R. M. Hare]], [[Petrus Singer]].
Linea 15:
<div class="references-small"><references/></div>
 
== Bibliographia ==
* Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1976. Motive Utilitarianism. ''Journal of Philosophy'' 73(14):467.
* Alican, Necip Fikri. 1994. ''Mill’s Principle of Utility: A Defense of John Stuart Mill’s Notorious Proof.'' Rodopi B. V. ISBN 9789051837483.
Linea 30:
* Goodin, Robert E. 1991. Utility and the good. ''The Blackwell Companion to Ethics'', ed. Peter Singer, cap. 20. Blackwell.
* Goodin, Robert E. 1995. ''Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy.'' Cambridge University Press.
* Habib, Allen. [[2008]]. [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/promises/ Promises]. In ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.''
* {{cite book |last = Halevy|first = Elie|title = The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism|year = 1966|publisher = Beacon Press|isbn = 0191010200}}
* {{cite journal |last = Hall |first = Everett W. |title = The 'Proof' of Utility in Bentham and Mill |journal = Ethics |issue = 60:1–18 |year = 1949 |jstor=2378436 |doi:10.1086/290691}}
Line 40 ⟶ 39:
* Hooker, Brad. 2002. ''Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality.'' Clarendon Press.
* Hooker, Brad & Timothy Chappell, eds. 2011. ''The problem of moral demandingness: new philosophical essays.'' Palgrave Macmillan. Praecioue capitulum 8: The Demandingness Objection. ISBN 9780230219403.
* {{cite book |last = Hume|first = David|editor-first = J. B.|editor-last = Schneewind|title = Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant|publisher = Cambridge University Press |year = 2002 |chapter = An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals |isbn = 9780521003049}}
* {{cite book |last = Hutcheson|first = Francis|editor-first = J. B.|editor-last = Schneewind|title = Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant|publisher = Cambridge University Press |year = 2002 |chapter = The Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue |isbn = 9780521003049}}
* {{cite book |last = Kagan | first = Shelly | title = The Limits of Morality (Oxford Ethics Series) | publisher = Clarendon Press |date= 1991 | isbn = 9780198239161}}
*Kagan, Shelly. [[1984]]. Does Consequentialism Demand too Much? Recent Work on the Limits of Obligation. ''Philosophy & Public Affairs'' 13(3). JSTOR 2265413.
Line 49 ⟶ 46:
* McCloskey, H. J. 1963. A Note on Utilitarian Punishment. ''Mind'' 72: 599
* McCloskey, H. J. 1957. An Examination of Restricted Utilitarianism. ''Philosophical Review'' 66:466–485.
* Mei, Y. P. 1934. ''Mo-tse, the Neglected Rival of Confucius.'' Arthur Probsthain.
* Mill, John Stuart. 1861. ''Utilitarianism.'' Fourth edition, Longmans, Gree, Reader, and Dyer, 1871.
* Moore, G. E. 1903. ''Principia Ethica.'' Prometheus Books.
* Nagel, Thomas. 2012. ''The Possibility of Altruism.'' Princeton University Press. Nova ed.
* Norcross, Alastair. [[2009]]. Two Dogmas of Deontology: Aggregation, Rights and the Separateness of Persons. ''Social Philosophy and Policy'' 26:76. doi:10.1017/S0265052509090049. [http://homepage.mac.com/anorcross/papers/2Dogmasdeontology.pdf Textus (PDF).]
* {{cite book |last = Oliphant,|first = Jill |title = OCR Religious Ethics for AS and A2 |publisher = Routledge |year = 2007}}
* {{cite book |last = Paley|first = William|editor-first = J. B.|editor-last = Schneewind|title = Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant|publisher = Cambridge University Press |year = 2002 |chapter = The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy |isbn = 9780521003049}}
* Parfit, Derek. 1986. ''Reasons and Persons.'' Oxford Paperbacks.
* Pettit, Philip. 1991. Consequentialism. ''The Blackwell Companion to Ethics'', ed. Peter Singer, cap. 19. Blackwell.